The Land of Non-Being - Wagner and Nirvana
I have now become exclusively preoccupied with a man who — albeit only in literary form — has entered my lonely life like a gift
from heaven. It is Arthur Schopenhauer, the greatest philosopher since Kant, whose ideas — as he himself puts it — he is the first person to think through to
their logical conclusion. The German professors have — very wisely — ignored him for 40 years; he was recently rediscovered — to Germany's shame — by an English critic. What
charlatans all these Hegels etc. are beside him! His principal idea, the final denial of the will to live, is of terrible seriousness, but it is uniquely redeeming. Of course it did not strike me as
anything new, and nobody can think such a thought if he has not already lived it. But it was this philosopher who first awakened the idea in me with such clarity. When I think back on the storms that
have buffeted my heart and on its convulsive efforts to cling to some hope in life — against my own better judgement — indeed, now that these storms have swelled so often to the fury of a
tempest, — I have yet found a sedative which has finally helped me to sleep at night: it is the sincere and heartfelt yearning for death: total unconsciousness, complete annihilation, the end of
all dreams — the only ultimate redemption! 
[R. Wagner to F. Liszt, 16? December 1854, tr. Spencer and Millington]
Without Schopenhauer the creation of Tristan und Isolde and Parsifal is unthinkable, out of the
question, for essential to their substance are metaphysical insights which Wagner had indeed absorbed into his living tissue and made authentically his own but which he would have been wholly incapable
of arriving at by himself. 
[Bryan Magee, Wagner and Philosophy (also available as The Tristan Chord), p. 193]
Several scholars have shown that seeds of the love tragedy theme — of the profound, often perplexing, Eros renunciation interplay
— were present in Wagner's works long before he had read Schopenhauer, Burnouf or Köppen.

[Guy R. Welbon, The Buddhist Nirvana and its Western Interpreters, 1968, p.179]
Renunciation in one form or another runs through all Wagner's works from The Flying Dutchman to Parsifal. The Dutchman
gains redemption, according to Wagner's explanation of the plot, "through a woman who shall sacrifice herself for the love of him. Thus it is the yearning for death that spurs him on to seek this
woman." 
[Elliot Zuckerman, The First Hundred Years of Wagner's Tristan, p.34]
Wagner formulates two different answers to unattainable love: union and fulfilment in death as in Tristan und Isolde, and complete
renunciation and union on a higher plane as in Die Sieger. 
[Carl Suneson, Richard Wagner och den indiska tankevärlden, 1985]
n the final act of Die Sieger, the Chandala girl Prakriti is offered a difficult choice by the
Buddha (Gautama Shakyamuni). For the first time the Buddha will accept a woman into the religious community, if Prakriti will accept a life of chastity and
humility. So she can join her beloved Ananda, but only after she has renounced sex. Prakriti chooses
renunciation so that she can be with Ananda, not as his wife or lover, but as a sister. (Later, for no obvious reason, Wagner changed the name of the
character to Savitri, the name of the heroine of an entirely separate story.)
Köppen's account of the Buddha's decision to admit women into the order stressed the Buddha's initial refusal and the role played by Ananda
in causing him to reverse that prohibition. Wagner chose to see in this final decision the [final] perfection of the Buddha himself — the redeemer redeemed — "one final advance to
consummate perfection. Ananda, standing nearer to life as yet, and directly affected by the young Chandala maiden's impetuous love, becomes the medium of this last perfecting". 
[Guy R. Welbon, The Buddhist Nirvana and its Western Interpreters, 1968, p.179]
n the words quoted above, written to Mathilde Wesendonk, Wagner means, beyond any doubt, the perfection of wisdom,
prajñāpāramitā (प्रज्ञापारमिता), which his (fictional) Buddha Shakyamuni obtains through compassion for the outcast maiden Prakriti.
It is a beautiful feature in the legend, that shows the Victoriously Perfect [der Siegreich Vollendete ] at last determined
to admit the woman. [In the margin:] Love — Tragedy. 
[R. Wagner, On the Womanly in the Human, February 1883. The very last words that Wagner wrote.]
Where Schopenhauer advocates withdrawal and non-cooperation in order to impose one's own meaning on the essential
meaninglessness of life, Wagner's lovers rush to embrace this will with such abandon and vigour that it is difficult to tell whether the force is overcoming the individuals or the individuals are
momentarily mastering the force. 
[A. Goldman and E. Sprinchorn, Wagner on Music and Drama, p.28]
For much of the time when Tristan and Isolde are not narrating or recalling they are gasping their longing for one another. The German word
for longing (Sehnen, with a capital as a noun and a small 's' as a verb) provides the focal concept of the Tristan libretto in the same way as Mitleid ('compassion') is the
focal concept of the Parsifal libretto; and in each case there is an elaborate substructure underpinning it in the form of Schopenhauer's philosophy, for longing is
the key concept of Schopenhauer's metaphysics of existence, and compassion the key concept of his ethics. 
[Bryan Magee, Wagner and Philosophy (also available as The Tristan Chord), p. 215]
n what many have regarded as Wagner's most Schopenhauerian work, Tristan und Isolde, the composer worked out his derivative of Schopenhauer's philosophy. Here is the romantic death- wish, again, expanded into a philosophy or even perhaps, as Michael Tanner has
suggested, a religion. Although there is no obvious Indian model for any of the text, Isolde's ecstatic transfiguration, with which the work ends, uses (like the 1856 ending of Götterdämmerung)
language strongly suggesting the influence of Indian religious literature and Buddhist or Brahmin concepts of deliverance.
t is a frequently encountered view of Wagner's engagement with the ideas of Schopenhauer and Indian
religion respectively, that sees Tristan und Isolde as the drama most affected by these influences. Even in Guy R. Welbon's study, it is
Tristan that is Welbon's focus of attention when he discusses Wagner. Bryan Magee's recent comment, above, redresses the balance. Schopenhauer was equally important
as the inspiration for Tristan and for Parsifal, although in the latter case Burnouf and Wolfram too were key
elements at the creative moment. As Bryan Magee knows, Schopenhauer insisted that his metaphysics and his ethics were inseparable. It should be noted that the key difference
between Tristan and Parsifal is one of emphasis: where the former emphasizes metaphysical ideas, the latter emphasizes ethical ideas. Specifically, those of Schopenhauer's essay On the Basis of Morality, in which, as Magee remarked above, the key concept of his ethics is compassion.
t might also be argued that there are no specifically Buddhist ideas in Tristan. Both Günter Lanczkowski and Guy R. Welbon have suggested that there are, while Carl Suneson was
sceptical. On internal evidence alone, it is not clear whether either Tristan or Isolde find deliverance at the end of the drama, and perhaps Wagner did not consider the question important. The subject
of his Tristan und Isolde is not salvation but the suffering caused by the desire for extinction. Whether that deliverance or extinction takes the form of absorption into Brahman or transition
into nirvāṇa (Sanskrit: निर्वाण, nirvāṇa; Pali: nibbāna), is unimportant, in the context of the drama. From a remark that Wagner made to Cosima many years later, that Kundry had
undergone Isolde's transfiguration a thousand times, it would appear that he had reached the view that Isolde had not yet escaped from saṃsarā (संसार), which in notes in the
Brown Book he equated to the realm of day; in contrast, nirvāṇa was the realm of night. So there is sufficient evidence from which
to conclude that, if not during the composition of Tristan und Isolde then at least in reflecting on it later, Wagner thought of Tristan yearning for nirvāṇa1.
agner's Parsifal deals with (among other Buddhist concepts) saṃsarā (the cycle of rebirth, which can be
heard in the music of Kundry) and deliverance or redemption from this cycle of rebirth. Although in some contexts the word saṃsarā might be translated as "world", or as existence
in the world, it can also mean "wandering". In one passage in the second act, after the critical kiss, Kundry and Parsifal speak of desire as burning. In his Fire Sermon the Buddha used burning as a metaphor for suffering. In the most widely accepted etymology of
nirvāṇa, the word means blowing out, as in the blowing out of a flame. Therefore, at least on etymological arguments, nirvāṇa is the end of suffering, the
blowing out of the flame when it is no longer fuelled by ignorance and desire. In Parsifal there is more than a hint of a sub-text about nirvāṇa. It is difficult to avoid
the conclusion that, unlike Isolde, 4 is released from saṃsarā into nirvāṇa, not by her own
efforts but by the intervention of a Bodhisattva, namely, Parsifal.
The bodhisattva doctrine includes a description of the transfer of merit [Sanskrit: punya] from a bodhisattva to those in need of
help. The being who receives this help is freed from further rebirth and the consequences of their actions in earlier lives, karma, are not brought to maturity but absorbed
in the depths of the bodhisattva's boundless sea of mercy. 
[Carl Suneson, Richard Wagner och den indiska tankevärlden, 19852]
sthoff is surely right when he says of Kundry: her deliverance [Erlösung] is extinction
in the Buddhist sense . None of the other commentators on Parsifal have given this sub-text any attention. Reciprocally, it is the compassion awakened in Parsifal by Kundry, in exact analogy
to Wagner's treatment of the Buddha and Prakriti, that brings to Parsifal the medium of his last perfecting.
n a recently published and thoughtful essay3, Ulrike Kienzle has expressed the view that
the realm of night in Tristan und Isolde is equivalent to nirvāṇa (as it was understood by Wagner, that is, the "selige Nichts"). Kienzle points to the entry in the
Brown Book, mentioned in my article above, in which Wagner equated nirvāṇa to night and saṃsarā to day.
Although Kienzle claims that Isolde enters into nirvāṇa at the end of the opera, this idea is difficult to reconcile with Wagner's statement that Kundry had undergone Isolde's
transfiguration a thousand times.
Footnote 1: Various recent commentators on Tristan u. Isolde have mentioned that the rising phrase which opens that score was prefigured in an orchestral fantasy by Hans von Bülow
which Wagner was studying in October 1854 (see his letter to von Bülow of 26 October), shortly before he made his first sketches for Tristan u. Isolde. The title of the fantasy is
Nirwana, opus 20. This shows how ideas about nirvāṇa and saṃsarā were very much current in Wagner's circle of friends and colleagues. Also that
these ideas were associated with Tristan u. Isolde from the very beginning.
Footnote 2: Suneson's brief discussion of the doctrine of the "transfer of merit" might have been based on his reading of primary sources but it is likely that his main source was the
summary of this doctrine in Har Dayal's The Bodhisattva Doctrine in Buddhist Sanskrit Literature, pages 188-193. Wagner probably came across this idea in Köppen's Die Religion des Buddha und ihre Entstehung. According to Dayal, in early Buddhism and contemporary Hinduism (Brahmanism) the doctrine of
karma was rigidly interpreted. The consequences of one's karma (actions) led to personal merit or demerit, which according to the Brahmins followed the ātman
(soul) through successive rebirths. In Buddhism too it was emphasised that the consequences of actions were inescapable; every man or woman reaps as he or she has sown. This idea was used by Wagner in
developing his scenarios for Die Sieger (where the one who carries a burden of sin or demerit is Prakriti) and Parsifal (where the one burdened is Kundry) respectively.
It was generally regarded as a hard teaching and both in later Buddhism and in Hinduism it was softened. In Mahāyāna Buddhism the doctrine of "transfer of merit" became widespread
and it became one (the seventh) of the pāramitās of the advanced Bodhisattva, who willingly gives away the merit that he has earned by his good works for the benefit of others.
Footnote 3: Wagner Spectrum: Schwerpunkt 'Wagner und der Buddhismus', 2007, page 47.
Footnote 4: I am probably not alone in puzzling over the fact that Kundry is still alive at the end of the Good Friday scene, even though both text and music suggest that she has reached
her goal of deliverance. The answer to this puzzle might be that Kundry remains in the world but she is no longer of the world. This can be related to the two kinds of nirvāṇa
described variously in some schools of Buddhism. The Theravada tradition identifies two types of nirvāṇa: sopadhishesa-nirvana, literally " nirvāṇa
with a remainder", attained and maintained during life, and anupadhishesa-nirvana, meaning " nirvāṇa without remainder" or final nirvana, achieved on death, a death which is not
followed by a rebirth or reincarnation. The Buddha Shakyamuni is believed to have reached both these states, the first at his Enlightenment under the Bodhi Tree, and the latter at his death many years
later. Most Mahayana schools have broadly similar ideas, but prefer the terms "abiding" and "non-abiding nirvana" for the two stages. Therefore I think we can regard Kundry as entering into
"abiding" nirvāṇa during the Good Friday music but later dying in the Temple, never to be reborn.
|